Paradoja del nihilismo

De Wikipedia, la enciclopedia libre

La paradoja del nihilismo se refiere a los aspectos contradictorios del nihilismo. Hay numerosas variantes de la paradoja.

Significado[editar]

De acuerdo con Hegarty, la "ausencia de sentido" muestra un cierto sentido.[1]

Verdad[editar]

Luhmann construye la paradoja ya que conociendo el significado y sentido del nihilismo, consecuentemente solo lo que es verdad podría ser verdad.[2]​ En un pie de página de su tesis, Slocombe iguala el nihilismo con la Paradoja del mentiroso.[3]

Religión[editar]

Riva localiza la paradoja en el hecho de la "actitud conservadora del catolicismo" desarrollada como reacción al nihilismo de Nietzsche, que a su vez revela una forma de nihilismo como olvido forzado de la ambigüedad paradójica entre diferencia de la realidad y lo sagrado.[4]

Teoría crítica legal[editar]

En el ámbito de los estudios críticos del derecho, los argumentos utilizados para criticar la posición centrista, también determina la posición de estos estudios.[5]

Ética[editar]

De acuerdo con Bornemark, «la paradoja del nihilismo es la opción para continuar con la vida de uno mismo afirmando que no vale más que cualquier otra vida».[6]​ Wright ve relativismo en la raíz de la paradoja.[7]

Véase también[editar]

Referencias[editar]

  1. Hegarty, Paul (2006). «Noise Music» (PDF). The Semiotic Review of Books (955 Oliver Road, Thunder Bay, Ontario, Canada P7B 5E1: Department of Sociology, Lakehead University) 16 (1-2): 2. ISSN 0847-1622. Consultado el 4 de abril de 2010. «Failure/impossibility: noise is only ever defined against something else, operating in the absence of meaning, but caught in the paradox of nihilism – that the absence of meaning seems to be some sort of meaning.» 
  2. Luhmann, Niklas (1 de febrero de 2002). «2 The Modernity of Science». En Rasch, William; Bal, Mieke; de Vries, Hent, eds. Theories of Distinction: Redescribing the Descriptions of Modernity. Cultural memory in the present. William Rasch (introduction), translations by Joseph O'Neil, Elliott Schreiber, Kerstin Behnke, William Whobrey. Stanford University Press. p. 64. ISBN 9780804741231. OCLC 318368737. Consultado el 4 de abril de 2010. «... the loss of reference had to appear as a loss of truth, resulting in the paradox of “nihilism,” which states that consequently only the untrue could be truth.» 
    The quoted chapter was originally published as Luhmann, Niklas; Behnke, Kerstin (1994). «The Modernity of Science». En Oppenheimer, Andrew, ed. New German Critique (New York: TELOS Press) (61 Special Issue on Niklas Luhmann (Winter 1994)): 9-23. ISSN 1558-1462. OCLC 50709608. Consultado el 4 de abril de 2010. 
    There is a 2002 review of the book Archivado el 7 de marzo de 2009 en Wayback Machine. in Canadian Journal of Sociology Online.
  3. Slocombe, Will (septiembre de 2003). Postmodern Nihilism: Theory and Literature (PDF). PhD theses from Aberystwyth University. University of Wales Aberystwyth. p. 154. Consultado el 5 de abril de 2010. «'There is no truth' is not inherently paradoxical. If it is considered true, then it creates a paradox because it is therefore false. However, if it is considered false, then no such paradox exists. Therefore, it is only when considered true that it creates a paradox, in much the same way as critics suggest that nihilism must be invalid for this very reason. Having now introduced this stronger formulation of nihilism, from this point on nihilism can be considered equivalent to the statement that 'This sentence is not true'. (footnote 110)». 
    A revised version was published as Slocombe, Will (2006). Nihilism and the Sublime Postmodern : The (Hi)Story of a Difficult Relationship From Romanticism to Postmodernism. Routledge. ISBN 9780415975292. OCLC 62281496. Consultado el 5 de abril de 2010. 
  4. Rivas, Virgilio Aquino (2008). «The Role of the Church in the Politics of Social Transformation: The Paradox of Nihilism» (PDF). Политикологија религије (Politics and Religion) (11000 Beograd (Belgrade, Serbia): Centar za proučavanje religije i versku toleranciju, 27.marta 95 (Center for Studies of Religion and Religious Tolerance)) II (2): 53-77. ISSN 1820-659X. Archivado desde el original el 15 de julio de 2011. Consultado el 4 de abril de 2010. 
  5. Belliotti, Raymond A. (1987). «critical legal studies: the paradoxes of indeterminacy and nihilism» (PDF). Philosophy & Social Criticism 13 (2): 145-154. doi:10.1177/019145378701300203. Consultado el 4 de abril de 2010. «... Critical Legal Studies Movement (CLS) ... CLS' view generates a "paradox of nihilism" which CLS has recognized and tried unsuccessfully to resolve.» 
    Belliotti, Raymond A. (25 de enero de 1994). Justifying Law: The Debate Over Foundations, Goals, and Methods. Temple University Press. p. 169. ISBN 9781566392037. Consultado el 4 de abril de 2010. «The argument supporting CLS' attack on centrist ideology, adhering as it does to social contingency, jurisprudential indeterminacy, and pervasive conditionality flowing from the fundamental contradiction, seems to preclude CLS from establishing a normative justification for its own vision. CLS' critical attack seems to cut the heart from all efforts to provide non-question-begging adjudication of epistemological and moral truth claims. This nihilistic paradox, in which CLS' critical attack is so extreme that it prohibits CLS from constructing persuasively its own alternative vision, ...» 
  6. Bornemark, Jonna (2006). «Limit-situation: Antinomies and Transcendence in Karl Jaspers’ Philosophy» (PDF). sats - Nordic Journal of Philosophy 7 (2). ISSN 1600-1974. Archivado desde el original el 5 de marzo de 2012. Consultado el 5 de abril de 2010. 
  7. Wright, Richard Ian (abril de 1994). The Dream of Enlightenment: An Essay on the Promise of Reason and Freedom in Modernity (PDF). Universit of British Columbia. Consultado el 5 de abril de 2010. «But essentially these values can be negated by extending the same critical methods which Marx uses to negate earlier philosophical idealism and liberal bourgeois ideology. In other words, from a Nietzschean perspective, Marx's foundational principles are not sufficient to defend his humanistic values. Thus it can be argued that they still maintain the residue of the Christian ethics and Platonic metaphysics which have permeated western thought for several thousand years and which continue to provide modem thinkers with many of their illusory presuppositions. Nevertheless, one is justified in asking: Without such presuppositions, does not the critique of law, politics, or "this earth" lose its ultimate justification or meaning? How can one critique laws without holding on to a sense of justice? And herein lies the crux of the paradox of nihilism. If nihilism is the basis of human existence then all values are relative, and as such, particular values can only be maintained through a "will to power." (page 97)».